Have one to sell?
Flip to back Flip to front
Listen Playing... Paused   You're listening to a sample of the Audible audio edition.
Learn more
See this image

Pure Immanence: Essays on a Life Hardcover – 3 Sep 2001


See all 2 formats and editions Hide other formats and editions
Amazon Price New from Used from
Hardcover
"Please retry"
£34.70 £9.99


Product details


More About the Author

Discover books, learn about writers, and more.

Product Description

Review

"A glimpse into some seminal themes of [Deleuze's] work. This book is worth purchasing for the Nietzsche essay alone." Jennifer Matey Metapsychology "Taken together, these essays are a sparkling and succinct affirmation of knowledge as something produced through myriad unexpected encounters and an ongoing assemblage of new multiplicities, where a life can never be fully or precisely specified, but remains indefinite and provisional, unfolding through an unending process of becoming." Jody Patterson Parachute

About the Author

Nuriye Nalan Sahin-Hodoglugil, M.D., M.P.H., M.A., is affiliated with the Hacettepe University School of Medicine, Public Health Department, Ankara, Turkey, and also with the Bay Area International Group, at the University of California, School of Public Health. She is the author of recent articles in Contraception and Sexually Transmitted Infections.

Inside This Book (Learn More)
Browse Sample Pages
Front Cover | Copyright | Table of Contents | Excerpt | Back Cover
Search inside this book:

What Other Items Do Customers Buy After Viewing This Item?

Customer Reviews

There are no customer reviews yet on Amazon.co.uk.
5 star
4 star
3 star
2 star
1 star

Most Helpful Customer Reviews on Amazon.com (beta)

Amazon.com: 3 reviews
34 of 39 people found the following review helpful
Eclectic Collection 1 Nov 2001
By A Customer - Published on Amazon.com
Format: Hardcover
This is the strangest assemblage of Deleuze's writings I have seen to date, though I am glad to have my hands on the Nietzsche article from '65, which nicely complements the Nietzsche monograph. It is very fine and extremely accessible introduction to Deleuze's idiosyncractic approach. The Hume piece is less strong; it is not Empiricism and Subjectivity. The first essay is trenchant, beautiful, and moving, penetrating what I had taken to be the heart of Deleuze's thought. A strong if uneven collection.
3 of 3 people found the following review helpful
From Dickens to Nietzsche 10 Feb 2013
By Wayne - Published on Amazon.com
Format: Paperback Verified Purchase
Charles Dickens captures the essence of the philosophical nature of reality according to Deluze.

Ellen Berry notes that "three brief essays make up Pure Immanence -- one on Hume, one on Nietzsche, and one -- "Immanence: A Life" -- that functions as a Deleuzian last testament of sorts, written as it was "in a strange interval [immediately] before his death" as John Rajchman informs us in his very useful introduction to the volume. In this essay, which appears first in the book, Deleuze defines what he calls a "transcendental empiricism," as a-subjective, impersonal, wild and powerful state, existing "in contrast to everything that makes up the world of the subject and the object".

Unlike a notion of the transcendent, the plane of the transcendental is an absolute immanence, complete in itself, neither "in something" nor belonging to someone (say some notion of a universal subject). "It is only when immanence is no longer immanence to anything other than itself that we can speak of a plane of immanence". Pure or absolute immanence is what Deleuze calls "A LIFE," defined as a paradoxical experience/duration in which individuality fades and becomes "a singular essence," an empty time of singularities or virtualities existing in between what we take to be the defining moments of an individual's life. A LIFE unfolds according to a different logic than the life of an individual. It can never be grasped fully; it is always yet "in the making," in potentia, and flashes into conscious existence only occasionally. Deleuze gives two striking examples to illustrate this enigmatic state/space/time, the first from Dickens's Our Mutual Friend:

"A disreputable man, a rogue, held in contempt by everyone, is found as he lies dying. Suddenly, those taking care of him manifest an eagerness, respect, even love, for his slightest sign of life. Everybody bustles about to save him, to the point where, in his deepest coma, this wicked man himself senses something soft and sweet penetrating him. But to the degree that he comes back to life, his saviors turn colder, and he becomes once again mean and crude. Between his life and his death, there is a moment that is only that of a life playing with death."

In another example, Deleuze calls attention to very small children, as yet unformed as individuals, who all tend to resemble one another except in their singularities -- a smile, a gesture. "Through all their sufferings and weakness, [they] are infused with an immanent life that is pure power and even bliss".

As Rajchman points out, one would need a new conception of society in order to understand Deleuze's notion of a life. It would be one in which we recognize that what we share is our singularities and not our individualities, that "what is common is impersonal and what is impersonal is common" (14). From this perspective, society is viewed not as a social contract between individuals but as an experiment with what in life precedes both individuals and collectivities. Relations with others would be based not in identification or recognition but in encounter and new compositions formed by saying "yes" to what is singular yet impersonal in living.

Berry notes that "This all too brief summary cannot do justice to what is a complex set of musings. While Pure Immanence is not the place to start if one is unfamiliar with Deleuze's thought, it is a rich, rewarding, and not inaccessible read."
----------------------------------------------------------------------------

Chapter Three is a brilliant summary of Nietzsche's project:

Nietzsche's Thus Spoke Zarathustra outlines three metamorphoses of the spirit 1) The camel which carries the weight of established values such as education, morality and culture 2)The lion which destroys and is the critique of all established values, and finally 3) the child of innocence carrying a mirror which reveals our monsterousness, who creates new values and new principles of evaluation.

An example of the creation of a new value is by observing that while illness is an evaluation of health, out of one's excessive well being, health can become the evaluation of illness through affirmation, even in the face of the illness--such is the "reversal," the "shift in perspective" that Nietzsche saw as crucial in the transmutation of values. It is this easy shift in perspectives from health to sickness and from sickness to health, this lightness of movement that signifies "great health."

"All interpretations determine the meaning of a phenomenon." Meaning consists of a relation of forces the active ones being valid (conquest and subjugation) and others being invalid and reactive (adaptation and regulation). Will is the relation of force to Force, but this doesn't mean that the will wants power or domination which becomes dependent on established values. The will to power consists not in coveting or even inn taking but in creating and giving. The power of will in not in having what we want but in our having the will to want.

Active forces affirm, and affirm in their difference (affirmation), while reactive forces principally negate, oppose, and limit the other (nihilism). While interpretation finds meaning in forces, evaluation finds values in the will to power.

The history of man and of nature has been the triumph of reactive forces, of negation, of adaptation (e.g., natural selection) and regulation. Slaves triumph in their subtracting and limiting others while "masters are slaves that have triumphed in a universal becoming-slave: European man, domesticated man, the buffon." When nihilism triumphs, the will to power stops meaning to create, and leads to want to dominate, to take on "established values: money, honors, power."

The typology, stages moving beyond the triumph of nihilism:

1) Resentment against everything that is active. Projection of blame--"It's your fault."
2) Bad Conscience. Introjection of blame--"It's my fault."
3) The ascetic ideal--Life, salvation is judged according to values that are said to be superior to life--lead to nothingness. The ascetic are carriers (donkey, buffoon) of the weight of responsibility to higher values, rather than the creative lightness of the dancer.
4) The death of God. The negation of the higher values are replaced by human values ("morals replace religion; utility, progress, even history replace divine values"). This is the higher man who claim to embrace all of reality, but are still carriers, burdened by human values (the Yes of the donkey).
5) The last man and the man who wants to die. The Last Man says all is vain, "better a nothingness of the will than a will to nothingness." Here is the "will to deny reactive life itself, and inspires in man the wish to actively destroy himself, a readiness for transmutation by "an active becoming of forces, a triumph of [the aggressivity that belongs to] affirmation in the will to power," like the "lightening that announces the thunder that follows, what is affirmed." "Joy emerges as the sole motive for philosophizing.

Stages of transmutation:

1) Multiplicity and becoming as objects of affirmation. "Joy [of the diverse, the multiple] emerges as the sole motive for philosophizing.
2) Becoming is no longer opposed to Being (the Being of becoming), the One is said of the multiple as multiple (the One of multiplicity). One affirms the necessity of chance, the player rolls the dice in affirmation.
3) The Eternal Return, not of the Same, but repetition of what can be affirmed beyond negation, the liberating. "I `must' want it in sucha a way that I also want its eternal return."
4) The Overman--the gathering of all that can be affirmed, the superior form of what is--Dionysus.
21 of 33 people found the following review helpful
I thought it explained something 10 Sep 2003
By Bruce P. Barten - Published on Amazon.com
Format: Hardcover
This book might be too *stigid* for you. The introduction quotes Deleuze on the nature of his philosophy, "... We will speak of a transcendental empiricism in contrast to everything that makes up the world of the subject and object." (p. 8, quoting Chapter One, Immanence: A Life, p. 25). For those who consider philosophy too confining to escape the metaphysics suggested by Kant, this might seem like a welcome suggestion, but the uniqueness of such a broad approach, as it might apply to changes in any particular life, is largely nebulous. Even Chapter Two, Hume, in which "A parallel conversion of science or theory follows: theory becomes an inquiry (the origin of this conception is in Francis Bacon; Immanuel Kant will recall it while transforming and rationalising it when he conceives of theory as a court or tribunal)" (pp. 35-36) is beyond my usual contemplation and "its attempt to reduce the paradox of relations;" (p. 37). The final chapter, on Nietzsche, strikes notes which I know well enough to become critical, and I find an assertion which must make this book more unique than most:
"Dialectics itself perpetuates this prestigiditation. Dialectics is the art that invites us to recuperate alienated properties." (p. 70).
Surely the right word for dialectics is prestidigitation, the sleight of hand that quickly moves things about to produce one thing where another was expected, but this book is produced in a world which is far more used to typing `prestige' when it has just been considering Kant, even if the paragraph preceding this unique assertion about dialectics ended with the kind of questions that Nietzsche was always throwing in Kant's direction:
"Who can really think that Kant reinstated critique or rediscovered the idea of the philosopher as legislator? Kant denounces false claims to knowledge, but he doesn't question the ideal of knowing; he denounces false morality, but he doesn't question the claims of morality or the nature and origin of its value. He blames us for having confused domains and interests; but the domains remain intact, and the interests of reason, sacred (true knowledge, true morals, true religion)." (p. 70).
Thorough knowledge of Nietzsche is indicated by the ability to make his philosophy illustrate the grand theme of "the symptoms of a decomposition." (p. 72). A key to this understanding is:
"Nietzsche is the first to tell us that killing God is not enough to set about the transmutation of values. In his work, there are at least fifteen versions of the death of God, all of them very beautiful." (pp. 71-72).
Going back to dialectics as prestigiditation, most people seem to be lost in the efforts to stigmatize, or hoping for stigmatism as a vision not subject to astigmatism, particularly "As long as the will to power is interpreted in terms of a `desire to dominate,' we inevitably make it depend on establish values, the only ones able to determine, in any case or conflict, who must be `recognized' as the most powerful. We then cannot recognize the nature of the will to power as an elastic principle of all of our evaluations, as a hidden principle for the creation of new values not yet recognized." (p. 73).
It might be possible to explain everything in this book by creating and giving value to words like *stigid* which unintentionally crept into the middle of a word in a complicated thought on the limits of the nature of philosophy. The complexity of transcendental empiricism might even relate to the explanation that Deleuze offers for "The will to power is the differential element from which derive the forces at work, as well as their respective quality in a complex whole." (p. 73). People who find this kind of thought too *stigid* for real mathematics, in which differential elements are usually determined easily if we know the formula from elementary calculus, but we rarely think about them otherwise, might not enjoy reading this book. People who already know a lot of Nietzsche will not be surprised to find, "Everywhere we see the victory of No over Yes, of reaction over action. Life becomes adaptive and regulative, reduced to its secondary forms; we no longer know what it means to act. Even the forces of the earth become exhausted on this desolate face." (p. 75). Perhaps the book has far more explanations than examples, and tends to emphasize the worst view of things overall, but it moves on, after "Zarathustra cries out his great disgust, his great contempt," (p. 90).
Were these reviews helpful? Let us know

Look for similar items by category


Feedback